Smith, Peter (2009): Induction, complexity, and economic methodology.
Preview |
PDF
MPRA_paper_12693.pdf Download (376kB) | Preview |
Abstract
This paper focuses on induction, because the supposed weaknesses of that process are the main reason for favouring falsificationism, which plays an important part in scientific methodology generally; the paper is part of a wider study of economic methodology. The standard objections to, and paradoxes of, induction are reviewed, and this leads to the conclusion that the supposed ‘problem’ or ‘riddle’ of induction is a false one. It is an artefact of two assumptions: that the classic two-valued logic (CL) is appropriate for the contexts in which induction is relevant; and that it is the touchstone of rational thought. The status accorded to CL is the result of historical and cultural factors. The material we need to reason about falls into four distinct domains; these are explored in turn, while progressively relaxing the restrictions that are essential to the valid application of CL. The restrictions include the requirement for a pre-existing, independently-guaranteed classification, into which we can fit all new cases with certainty; and non-ambiguous relationships between antecedents and consequents. Natural kinds, determined by the existence of complex entities whose characteristics cannot be unbundled and altered in a piecemeal, arbitrary fashion, play an important part in the review; so also does fuzzy logic (FL). These are used to resolve two famous paradoxes about induction (the grue and raven paradoxes); and the case for believing that conventional logic is a subset of fuzzy logic is outlined. The latter disposes of all questions of justifying induction deductively. The concept of problem structure is used as the basis for a structured concept of rationality that is appropriate to all four of the domains mentioned above. The rehabilitation of induction supports an alternative definition of science: that it is the business of developing networks of contrastive, constitutive explanations of reproducible, inter-subjective (‘objective’) data. Social and psychological obstacles ensure the progress of science is slow and convoluted; however, the relativist arguments against such a project are rejected.
Item Type: | MPRA Paper |
---|---|
Original Title: | Induction, complexity, and economic methodology |
Language: | English |
Keywords: | induction; economics; methodology; complexity |
Subjects: | B - History of Economic Thought, Methodology, and Heterodox Approaches > B4 - Economic Methodology > B41 - Economic Methodology |
Item ID: | 12693 |
Depositing User: | Peter Smith |
Date Deposited: | 13 Jan 2009 08:03 |
Last Modified: | 02 Oct 2019 00:57 |
References: | [1] Fox, G (1997) Reason and reality in the methodologies of economics : an introduction. Edward Elgar. [2] Blaug, M (1980) The Methodology of Economics, or, How Economists Explain. Cambridge. [3] Hausman, DM (1992) The Separate and Inexact Science of Economics. Cambridge. [4] Anderson. AR, and Belnap, N (1975) Entailment: the logic of relevance and necessity. Princeton University Press. [5] Mill, JS (1967) A system of logic, ratiocinative and inductive,: Being a connected view of the principles of evidence and the methods of scientific investigation. Longmans. [6] Hill, GC, and Holman, JS (1983) Chemistry in Context, Chapter 3. Nelson. [7] O’Sullivan, PJ (1987) Economic Methodology and the Freedom to Choose, page 44. Routledge. [8] Quine, WVO (1966) Word and Object. Chicago. [9] Stalker, D (ed.) (1992) Grue! The New Riddle of Induction. Open Court Publishing. [10] Gabbay, D, and Woods, J (Eds) (2004) Handbook of the History of Logic. Elsevier. [11] Quine, WVO ( 1951) Two Dogmas of Empiricism. In: Quine, WVO ( 1951) From a Logical Point of View. Harvard University Press. [12] Lindsay, AD (1936) Kant, Chapter 3. (Ernest Benn Ltd, London.) [13] Mises, L von (1962) The ultimate Foundation of Economic Science: An Essay on Method, Chapter 2. Van Nostrand. [14] Robbins, L (1984) The nature and Significance of Economic Science, p79ff. Macmillan. [15] Holmes, EC (1955) The Kantian Views on Space and Time Re-evaluated. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 16, (2), 240-244. [16] Barrow, JD (1988) The World Within The World, p150ff. Oxford University Press. [17] Brock, WH (1992) The Fontana History of Chemistry. Fontana [18] Bannister, D, and Fransella, F (1992) Inquiring Man: The Theory of Personal Constructs. Routledge. [19] Raven, PH, et al (2005) Biology, Chapter 26. McGraw-Hill. [20] Mintzberg, H (1983) Power In and Around Organizations, Chapter 13. Prentice-Hall. [21] Bailey, FG (2001) Treasons, Stratagems and Spoils: How Leaders Make Practical Use of Beliefs and Values. Westview Press. [22] Kornblith , H (1995) Inductive Inference and Its Natural Ground: An Essay in Naturalistic Epistemology. MIT Press. [23] Quine, WVO, In Stalker (1992), op cit. [24] Raven et al (2005) Chapter 14. [25] Srivasatava, PK (2008) Could Our Own Proteins Be Used to Help Us Fight Cancer? Scientific American, July 2008. [26] Aristotle (J Barnes, Ed) (2003) Aristotle’s Ethics. Folio Society. [27] Ross, TJ (1995) Fuzzy Logic With Engineering Applications. (McGraw Hill.) [28] Smith, PJ (2008) New Perspectives on Realism, Tractability, and Complexity in Economics, p 19ff. IDPM Working Paper, Institute for Development Policy and Management, University of Manchester. [29] McNeill, D and Freiberger, P (1994). Fuzzy Logic, p 117ff. (Simon and Schuster.) [30] Olson, JS (1999) Historical Dictionary of the 1960s, p65, entry for Body Count. Greenwood Publishing. [31] Mandelbrot, BB and Hudson, RL (2005) The (Mis)Behaviour of Markets: A Fractal View of Risk, Ruin and Reward. Profile Books. [32] Terano, T, Kiyoji, A, and Sugeno, M (1994) Applied Fuzzy Systems. (Trans. by C Aschmann.) AP Professional, Boston. [33] Robbins (1984), p 138ff. [34] Smith (2008), p 19ff. [35] Elkan, C (1993) The Paradoxical Success of Fuzzy Logic, in Proceedings of the Eleventh National Conference on Artificial Intelligence, 698-703. IEEE. [36] Haack, S (1996) Deviant Logic, Fuzzy Logic: Beyond the Formalism, p 233ff. University of Chicago Press. [37] Haack, S (1994) Evidence and Inquiry: Towards Reconstruction in Epistemology. Blackwell. [38] Greer, WB (2000) The Economics of JM Keynes and FH Knight. Edward Elgar. [39] Alston, JA (Ed) (1998) Science Under Scarcity: Principles and Practice for Agricultural Research Evaluation and Priority Setting. CABI Publishing. [40] Janis IL, and Mann L (1977) Decision Making: A Psychological Analysis of Conflict, Choice, and Commitment. Free Press/ Macmillan. [41] Nutt, PC (1989) Making Tough Decisions: Tactics for Improving Managerial Decision Making. Jossey-Bass. [42] Mitroff, II (1974) The Subjective Side of Science, Chapter 7. Elsevier. [43] Smith, PJ (2001) Priority Setting in Agricultural Research: Beyond Economic Surplus Methods. Public Administration and Development, 21, 419-428. [44] Feyerabend, PK (1978) Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge. Verso. [45] Green, EH (2002) Ideologies of Conservatism: Conservative Political Ideas In The Twentieth Century. Oxford University Press. [46] Popper, K (2002) The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Routledge Classics. [47] Popper, K (2002) Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge. Routledge Classics. [48] Lipton, P (2004) Inference to the Best Explanation. Routledge. [49] Schank, RC (1986) Explanation patterns : understanding mechanically and creatively. Erlbaum Associates. [50] Large, EC (1950) Advance of the Fungi. Jonathan Cape. [51] Oldroyd, D (1990) The Highlands Controversy. University of Chicago. [52] Sober, E, and Wilson, DS (1998) Unto Others: The Evolution of Unselfish Behavior. (Harvard.) [53] Grayling, AC (2007) Truth, Meaning, and Realism, Chapters 8 and 9. Continuum. [54] Kuhn, T (1970) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. University of Chicago. [55]Iacoboni, M (2007) Mirroring People: The New Science of How We Connect With Others, p 10ff. [56] Lakatos, I (1970) Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes. In Lakatos, I and Musgrave, A (1990) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. (Cambridge University Press.) [57] Laudan, L (1977) Progress and its Problems: Towards a theory of scientific growth. (University of California, Berkeley.) [58] Couvalis, G (1998) The Philosophy of Science: Science and Objectivity, Chapter 1. Sage. [59] Wilson, DS and Wilson, OE (1997)Rethinking the Theoretical Foundation of Sociobiology. Quarterly Review of Biology, 82, (4), 327 – 348. [60] Barnes, B and Bloor, D (1982) Relativism, Rationalism, Sociology of Knowledge. In Hollis, M and Lukes, S (1882) Rationality and Relativism. Blackwell [61] Whorf, Benjamin (Ed. J Carroll) (1956). Language, Thought, and Reality: Selected Writings of Benjamin Lee Whorf, p 212ff. MIT Press. [62] Gumperz, J, and Levinson, S (Eds.) Rethinking Linguistic Relativity. Cambridge University Press. 1996 [63] Sapir, Edward. (Ed. DG Mandelbaum) (1983). Selected Writings of Edward Sapir in Language, Culture, and Personality. University of California Press. [64a] Sober, E, and Wilson, DS (1998) Unto Others: The Evolution of Unselfish Behavior. (Harvard.) [64b] Smith (2008), Section 7. [65] Carter, R (2000) Mapping the Mind. Phoenix. |
URI: | https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/id/eprint/12693 |