Da Silva, Sergio and Matsushita, Raul and De Sousa, Maicon (2016): Utilitarian Moral Judgments Are Cognitively Too Demanding. Published in: Open Access Library Journal , Vol. 3, No. 2 (2016): pp. 1-9.
Preview |
PDF
MPRA_paper_69387.pdf Download (477kB) | Preview |
Abstract
We evaluate utilitarian judgments under the dual-system approach of the mind. In the study, participants respond to a cognitive reflection test and five (sacrificial and greater good) dilemmas that pit utilitarian and non-utilitarian options against each other. There is judgment reversal across the dilemmas, a result that casts doubt in considering utilitarianism as a stable, ethical standard to evaluate the quality of moral judgments. In all the dilemmas, participants find the utilitarian judgment too demanding in terms of cognitive currency because it requires non-automatic, deliberative thinking. In turn, their moral intuitions related to the automatic mind are frame dependent, and thus can be either utilitarian or non-utilitarian. This suggests that automatic moral judgments are about descriptions, not about substance.
Item Type: | MPRA Paper |
---|---|
Original Title: | Utilitarian Moral Judgments Are Cognitively Too Demanding |
Language: | English |
Keywords: | Cognitive Reflection, Utilitarianism, Moral Judgments |
Subjects: | B - History of Economic Thought, Methodology, and Heterodox Approaches > B4 - Economic Methodology > B41 - Economic Methodology |
Item ID: | 69387 |
Depositing User: | Sergio Da Silva |
Date Deposited: | 10 Feb 2016 06:02 |
Last Modified: | 26 Sep 2019 14:34 |
References: | [1] Bentham, J. (1789) An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. Clarendon Press, Oxford. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oseo/instance.00077240 [2] Mill, J.S. (1861) Utilitarianism and Other Essays. Penguin Books, London. [3] Baron, J. and Ritov, I. (2009) Protected Values and Omission Bias as Deontological Judgments. In: Bartels, D.M., Bauman, C.W., Skitka, L.J. and Medin, D.L., Eds., Moral Judgment and Decision Making: The Psychology of Learning and Motivation, Elsevier, San Diego, 133-167. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/s0079-7421(08)00404-0 [4] Greene, J.D., Cushman, F.A., Stewart, L.E., Lowenberg, K., Nystrom, L.E. and Cohen, J.D. (2009) Pushing Moral Buttons: The Interaction between Personal Force and Intention in Moral Judgment. Cognition, 111, 364-371. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2009.02.001 [5] Sunstein, C.R. (2005) Moral Heuristics. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28, 531-542. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X05000099 [6] Singer, P. (1979) Practical Ethics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. [7] Cushman, F., Young, L. and Greene, J.D. (2010) Our Multi-System Moral Psychology: Towards a Consensus View. In: Doris, J.M., Ed., Oxford Handbook of Moral Psychology, Oxford University Press, Oxford. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199582143.003.0003 [8] Greene, J.D. (2008) The Secret Joke of Kant’s Soul. In: Sinnott-Armstrong, W., Ed., Moral Psychology: The Neuroscience of Morality, MIT Press, Cambridge, 35-79. [9] Kahane, G. and Shackel, N. (2010) Methodological Issues in the Neuroscience of Moral Judgment. Mind and Language, 25, 561-582. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0017.2010.01401.x [10] Thomson, J.J. (1985) The Trolley Problem. Yale Law Journal, 94, 1395-1415. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/796133 [11] Bartels, D.M. and Pizarro, D.A. (2011) The Mismeasure of Morals: Antisocial Personality Traits Predict Utilitarian Responses to Moral Dilemmas. Cognition, 121, 154-161. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2011.05.010 [12] Kahane, G., Everett, J.A.C., Earp, B.D., Farias, M. and Savulescu, J. (2015) “Utilitarian” Judgments in Sacrificial Moral Dilemmas Do Not Reflect Impartial Concern for the Greater Good. Cognition, 134, 193-209. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2014.10.005 [13] Greene, J.D., Morelli, S.A., Lowenberg, K., Nystrom, L.E. and Cohen, J.D. (2008) Cognitive Load Selectively Interferes with Utilitarian Moral Judgment. Cognition, 107, 1144-1154. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2007.11.004 [14] Evans, J.S.B.T. (2008) Dual-Processing Accounts of Reasoning, Judgment, and Social Cognition. Annual Review of Psychology, 59, 255-278. http://dx.doi.org/10.1146/annurev.psych.59.103006.093629 [15] Frederick, S. (2005) Cognitive Reflection and Decision Making. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 19, 25-42. http://dx.doi.org/10.1257/089533005775196732 [16] Foot, P. (1967) The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of Double Effect. Oxford Review, 5, 5-15. [17] Moore, A.B., Clark, B.A. and Kane, M.J. (2008) Who Shalt Not Kill? Individual Differences in Working Memory Capacity, Executive Control, and Moral Judgment. Psychological Science, 19, 549-557. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9280.2008.02122.x [18] Hauser, M., Cushman, F., Young, L., Jin, R. and Mikhail, J. (2007) A Dissociation between Moral Judgments and Justifications. Mind & Language, 22, 1-21. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0017.2006.00297.x [19] Hare, R.M. (1981) Moral Thinking: Its Levels, Method, and Point. Oxford University Press, Oxford. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/0198246609.001.0001 [20] Kahneman, D. (2011) Thinking, Fast and Slow. Farrar, Straus and Giroux, New York. [21] Hagger, M.S., Wood, C., Stiff, C. and Chatzisarantis, N.L. (2010) Ego Depletion and the Strength Model of Self-Control: A Meta-Analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 136, 495-525. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0019486 [22] Greene, J.D., Nystrom, L.E., Engell, A.D., Darley, J.M. and Cohen, J.D. (2004) The Neural Bases of Cognitive Conflict and Control in Moral Judgment. Neuron, 44, 389-400. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.neuron.2004.09.027 |
URI: | https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/id/eprint/69387 |