Pivato, Marcus (2011): Voting rules as statistical estimators.
Preview |
PDF
MPRA_paper_30292.pdf Download (369kB) | Preview |
Abstract
We adopt an `epistemic' interpretation of social decisions: there is an objectively correct choice, each voter receives a `noisy signal' of the correct choice, and the social objective is to aggregate these signals to make the best possible guess about the correct choice. One epistemic method is to fix a probability model and compute the maximum likelihood estimator (MLE), maximum a posteriori estimator (MAP) or expected utility maximizer (EUM), given the data provided by the voters. We first show that an abstract voting rule can be interpreted as MLE or MAP if and only if it is a scoring rule. We then specialize to the case of distance-based voting rules, in particular, the use of the median rule in judgement aggregation. Finally, we show how several common `quasiutilitarian' voting rules can be interpreted as EUM.
Item Type: | MPRA Paper |
---|---|
Original Title: | Voting rules as statistical estimators |
Language: | English |
Keywords: | voting; maximum likelihood estimator; maximum a priori estimator; expected utility maximizer; statistics; epistemic democracy; Condorcet jury theorem; scoring rule |
Subjects: | D - Microeconomics > D8 - Information, Knowledge, and Uncertainty > D81 - Criteria for Decision-Making under Risk and Uncertainty D - Microeconomics > D7 - Analysis of Collective Decision-Making > D70 - General C - Mathematical and Quantitative Methods > C4 - Econometric and Statistical Methods: Special Topics > C44 - Operations Research ; Statistical Decision Theory |
Item ID: | 30292 |
Depositing User: | Marcus Pivato |
Date Deposited: | 21 Apr 2011 12:06 |
Last Modified: | 01 Oct 2019 18:22 |
References: | Austen-Smith, D., Banks, J., 1996. Information aggregation, rationality, and the Condorcet jury theorem. American Political Science Review, 34-45. Balinski, M., Laraki, R., May 22 2007. A theory of measuring, electing, and ranking. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science 104 (21), 8720-8725. Balinski, M., Laraki, R., 2011. Majority Judgment: Measuring, Ranking, and Electing. MIT Press, Boston, MA. Ben-Yashar, R., Paroush, J., 2001. Optimal decision rules for fixed-size committees in polychotomous choice situations. Soc. Choice Welf. 18 (4), 737-746. Black, D. S., 1948. On the rationale of group decision-making. J. Political Economy 56, 23-34. Bohman, J., Rehg, W. (Eds.), 1997. Deliberative Democracy : Essays on Reason and Politics. MIT Press. Bovens, L., Rabinowicz, W., 2006. Democratic answers to complex questions ---an epistemic perspective. Synthese 150 (1), 131-153. Brams, S. J., Fishburn, P. C., 1983. Approval voting. Birkhauser Boston, Mass. Buhlmann, H., Huber, P. J., 1963. Pairwise comparison and ranking in tournaments. Ann. Math. Statist. 34, 501-510. Cohen, A., Feigin, P., 1978. On a model of concordance between judges. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society B 40 (2), 203-213. Cohen, J., 1986. An epistemic conception of democracy. Ethics 97 (1), 26-38. Condorcet, M. d., 1785. Essai sur l'application de l'analyse a la probabilite des decisions rendues a la pluralite des voix. Paris. Conitzer, V., Rognlie, M., Xia, L., 2009. Preference functions that score rankings and maximum likelihood estimation. In: 21st International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (IJCAI-09). Pasadena, CA, pp. 109-115. Conitzer, V., Sandholm, T., 2005. Common voting rules as maximum likelihood estimators. In: 21st Annual Conference on Uncertainty in Artificial Intelligence (UAI-05). Edinburgh, pp. 145-152. Dietrich, F., Spiekerman, K., 2011. Epistemic democracy with defensible premises. (preprint). Drissi-Bakhkhat, M., 2002. A statistical approach to the aggregation of votes. Ph.D. thesis, Universite Laval, Quebec. Drissi-Bakhkhat, M., Truchon, M., 2004. Maximum likelihood approach to vote aggregation with variable probabilities. Soc. Choice Welf. 23 (2), 161-185. Estlund, D., 1997. Beyond fairness and deliberation: The epistemic dimension of democratic authority. In: Bohman and Rehg (1997), pp. 173-204. Fallis, D., June 2005. Epistemic value theory and judgment aggregation. Episteme 2 (1), 39-55. Fligner, M. A., Verducci, J. S., 1986. Distance based ranking models. J. Roy. Statist. Soc. Ser. B 48 (3), 359-369. Fligner, M. A., Verducci, J. S., 1988. Multistage ranking models. J. Amer. Statist. Assoc. 83 (403), 892-901. Fligner, M. A., Verducci, J. S., 1990. Posterior probabilities for a consensus ordering. Psychometrika 55 (1), 53-63. Fligner, M. A., Verducci, J. S. (Eds.), 1993. Probability models and statistical analysis for ranking data. Springer-Verlag. Folland, G. B., 1984. Real Analysis. John Wiley & Sons, New York. Hartman, S., Pigozzi, G., Sprenger, J., 2011. Relaible methods of judgement aggregation. (preprint). Hays, W. L., 1960. A note on average tau as a measure of concordance. J. Amer. Statist. Assoc. 55, 331-341. Hummel, P., 2010. Jury theorems with multiple alternatives. Soc. Choice Welf. 34 (1), 65-103. Kaniovski, S., 2010. Aggregation of correlated votes and Condorcet's jury theorem. Theory and Decision 69 (3), 453-468. Kemeny, J. G., Fall 1959. Math without numbers. Daedalus 88, 571-591. Kendall, M., 1938. A new measure of rank correlation. Biometrika 30, 81-93. Kendall, M. G., 1970. Rank Correlation Methods. Griffin, London. Lebanon, G., Lafferty, J., 2002. Cranking: Combining rankings using conditional models on permutations. In: International Conference on Machine Learning. pp. 363-370. List, C., June 2005. Group knowledge and group rationality: A judgment aggregation perspective. Episteme 2 (1), 25-38. List, C., Goodin, R. E., 2001. Epistemic democracy: Generalizing the Condorcet Jury Theorem. Journal of Political Philosophy 9 (3), 277-306. List, C., Pettit, P., 2002. Aggregating sets of judgements: an impossibility result. Economics and Philosophy 18, 89-110. List, C., Puppe, C., 2009. Judgement aggregation: a survey. In: Oxford handbook of rational and social choice. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK., pp. 457-482. Mallows, C. L., 1957. Non-null ranking models. I. Biometrika 44, 114-130. Miller, M. K., Osherson, D., 2009. Methods for distance-based judgment aggregation. Social Choice and Welfare 32 (4), 575-601. Myerson, R. B., 1995. Axiomatic derivation of scoring rules without the ordering assumption. Soc. Choice Welf. 12 (1), 59-74. Nehring, K., Pivato, M., Puppe, C., 2009. Condorcet-efficient judgement aggregation. (preprint). Pivato, M., 2011. Variable-population scoring rules. (preprint). Remage, Jr., R., Thompson, Jr., W. A., 1964. Rankings from paired comparisons. Ann. Math. Statist. 35, 739-747. Remage, Jr., R., Thompson, Jr., W. A., 1966. Maximum-likelihood paired comparison rankings. Biometrika 53, 143-149. Spearman, C., 1904. The proof and measurement of association between two things. American Journal of Psychology 15, 72-101. Truchon, M., 2008. Borda and the maximum likelihood approach to vote aggregation. Math. Social Sci. 55 (1), 96-102. Truchon, M., Gordon, S., 2008. Social choice, optimal inference and figure skating. Soc. Choice Welf. 30 (2), 265-284. Truchon, M., Gordon, S., 2009. Statistical comparison of aggregation rules for votes. Math. Social Sci. 57 (2), 199-212. Xia, L., Conitzer, V., Lang, J., 2010. Aggregating preferences in multi-issue domains by using maximum likelihood estimators. In: 9th International Joint Conference on Autonomous Agents and Multi Agent Systems (AAMAS-10). Toronto, pp. 399-406. Young, H. P., 1986. Optimal ranking and choice from pairwise decisions. In: Grofman, B., Owen, G. (Eds.), Information pooling and group decision making. JAI press, Greenwich, CT, pp. 113-122. Young, H. P., 1988. Condorcet's theory of voting. American Political Science Review 82 (4), 1231-1244. Young, H. P., Winter 1995. Optimal voting rules. Journal of Economic Perspectives 9 (1), 51-64. Young, H. P., 1997. Group choice and individual judgments. In: Mueller, D. C. (Ed.), Perspectives on public choice: A handbook. Cambridge UP, Cambridge, UK, Ch. 9, pp. 181-200. Young, H. P., Levenglick, A., 1978. A consistent extension of Condorcet's election principle. SIAM J. Appl. Math. 35 (2), 285-300. |
URI: | https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/id/eprint/30292 |