Koundouri, Phoebe and Pittis, Nikitas and Samartzis, Panagiotis (2023): Counterfactual Priors: A Bayesian Response to Ellsberg's Paradox. Published in:
Preview |
PDF
MPRA_paper_122027.pdf Download (235kB) | Preview |
Abstract
This paper analyzes the root cause of Ellsberg-type choices. This class of problems share the feature that at the time of the decision, t = m, the decision maker (DM) possesses partial information, Im, about the events/propositions of interest F: DM knows the objective probabilities of the sub-class F1, F1 С F only, whereas she is uninformed about the probabilities of the complement F’1 . As a result, DM may slip into the state of "comparative ignorance" (see Heath and Tve rsky 1991 and Fox and Tversky 1995). Under this state, DM is likely to exhibit "ambiguity aversion" (AA) for the events of F’1 relative to those of F1. AA, in turn results in DM having non-coherent beliefs, that is, her prior probability function, PI0m, is not additive. A possible way to mitigate AA is to motivate DM to form her prior in a state of "uniform ignorance". This may be accomplished by inviting DM to bring herself to the hypothetical time t = 0, in the context of which Im was still a contingency, and trace her "counterfactual prior", Pc0, "back then". Under uniform ignorance, DM may adhere to the "Principle of Indiference", thus identifying Pc0 with the uniform distribution. Once Pc0 is elicited, DM can embody the existing information Im into her current, actual set of beliefs Pm by means of Bayesian Conditionalization. In this case, we show that Pm is additive.
Item Type: | MPRA Paper |
---|---|
Original Title: | Counterfactual Priors: A Bayesian Response to Ellsberg's Paradox |
Language: | English |
Keywords: | JEL Classifcation: C44, D81, D83, D89 |
Subjects: | C - Mathematical and Quantitative Methods > C0 - General |
Item ID: | 122027 |
Depositing User: | Prof. Phoebe Koundouri |
Date Deposited: | 26 Sep 2024 13:30 |
Last Modified: | 26 Sep 2024 13:30 |
References: | Al-Najjar, N. I., and Weinstein, J. (2009). The ambiguity aversion literature: a critical assessment. Economics & Philosophy, 25(3), 249-284. Bertrand, J. (1889). Calcul des probabilites, 1st ed. (Gauthier-Villars, Paris). Carnap, R. (1962). Logical Foundations of Probability. 2nd ed. University of Chicago Press. Carnap, R. (1971). Inductive logic and rational decision. Studies in Inductive Logic and Probability, 1, 5-31. Cerreia-Vioglio, S., Maccheroni, F., Marinacci, M., and Montrucchio, L. (2011). Uncertainty averse preferences. Journal of Economic Theory, 146(4), 1275-1330. Cheng, X. (2022). Relative maximum likelihood updating of ambiguous beliefs. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 99, 102587. Chow, C. C., and Sarin, R. K. (2001). Comparative ignorance and the Ellsberg paradox. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 22, 129-139. Curley, S.P., Yates, J.F. and Abrams, R.A. (1986). Psychological sources of ambiguity avoidance. Organizational behavior and human decision processes, 38(2), 230-256. Ellsberg, D. (1961). Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 75, 643-669. Elster, J. (1979). Ulysses and the Sirens: Studies in Rationality and Irrationality. Cambridge University Press. Fox, C. R. and Tversky, A. (1995). Ambiguity aversion and comparative ignorance. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 110(3), 585-603. Gilboa, I., and Marinacci, M. (2016). Ambiguity and the Bayesian paradigm. Readings in formal epistemology, 385-439. Gilboa, I., and Schmeidler, D. (1993). Updating ambiguous beliefs. Journal of Economic Theory, 59(1), 33-49. Gilboa, I. and Scheidler, D. (1989). Maxmin expected utility with a nonunique prior. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 18, 141-153. Gul, F. and Pesendorfer, W. (2001). Temptation and self-control. Econometrica, 69(6), 1403-1435. Heath, C. and Tversky, A. (1991). Preference and belief: Ambiguity and competence in choice under uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 4(1), 5-28. Humphreys, M. S. and Revelle, W. (1984). Personality, motivation, and performance: a theory of the relationship between individual differences and information processing. Psychological Review, 91(2), 153-184. Jaynes, E. (1968). Prior probabilities. IEEE Transactions On Systems Science and Cybernetics, 4(3), 227-241. Leon, M. R. and Revelle, W. (1985). E§ects of anxiety on analogical reasoning: a test of three theoretical models. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 49(5), 1302-1315. Lewis, D. (1976). Probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabilities. Philosophical Review, 85, 297-315. Maccheroni, F., Marinacci, M., and Rustichini, A. (2006). Ambiguity aversion, robustness, and the variational representation of preferences. Econometrica, 74(6), 1447-1498. Meacham, C. J. (2016). Ur-priors, conditionalization, and ur-prior conditionalization. Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy, 3. Pahlke, M. (2022). Dynamic consistency in incomplete information games with multiple priors. Games and Economic Behavior, 133, 85-108. Pittis, N., Koundouri, P., Samartzis, P., Englezos, N., and Papandreou, A. (2021). Ambiguity aversion, modern Bayesianism and small worlds. Open Research Europe, 1, 13. Raiffa, H. (1961). Risk, Ambiguity, and the Savage Axioms: Comment. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 75(4), 690-694. Rosenkrantz, R. D. (1982). Does the philosophy of induction rest on a mistake? The Journal of Philosophy, 79(2), 78-97. Savage, L. (1954). The foundations of statistics. New-York, John Wiley. Scheidler, D. (1989). Subjective probability and expected utility without additivity. Econometrica, 57(3), 571ñ587. Skyrms, B. (1983). Zenoís paradox of measure. Physics, Philosophy and Psychoanalysis, 223-254. Strevens, M. (2017). Scientific Sharing: Communism and the Social Contract. Scientific Collaboration and Collective Knowledge, edited by Thomas Boyer- Kassem, Conor Mayo-Wilson and Michael Weisberg. Oxford University Press. Van Fraassen, B. C. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Clarendon Press. |
URI: | https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/id/eprint/122027 |