Navarro-Martinez, Daniel and Loomes, Graham and Isoni, Andrea and Butler, David and Alaoui, Larbi (2017): Boundedly Rational Expected Utility Theory.
Preview |
PDF
MPRA_paper_79893.pdf Download (865kB) | Preview |
Abstract
We build a satisficing model of probabilistic choice under risk which embeds Expected Utility Theory (EUT) into a boundedly rational deliberation process. The decision maker accumulates evidence for and against alternative options by repeatedly sampling from her underlying set of EU preferences until the evidence favouring one option satisfies her desired level of confidence. Notwithstanding its EUT core, the model produces patterns of behaviour that violate standard axioms, while at the same time capturing the systematic relationship between choice probabilities, response times and confidence judgments, which is beyond the scope of theories that do not take deliberation into account.
Item Type: | MPRA Paper |
---|---|
Original Title: | Boundedly Rational Expected Utility Theory |
Language: | English |
Keywords: | Expected utility; bounded rationality; deliberation; probabilistic choice; confidence; response times. |
Subjects: | D - Microeconomics > D0 - General > D03 - Behavioral Microeconomics: Underlying Principles D - Microeconomics > D8 - Information, Knowledge, and Uncertainty > D81 - Criteria for Decision-Making under Risk and Uncertainty |
Item ID: | 79893 |
Depositing User: | Dr Andrea Isoni |
Date Deposited: | 01 Aug 2017 05:19 |
Last Modified: | 26 Sep 2019 15:09 |
References: | Acemoglu, D. and Scott, A. (1994). Consumer confidence and rational expectations: Are agents’ beliefs consistent with the theory? Economic Journal, 104, 1–19. Achtziger, A. and Alós-Ferrer, C. (2014). Fast or rational? A response-time study of Bayesian updating. Management Science, 60(4), 923–938. Allais, M. (1953). Le comportement de l’homme rationnel devant le risque: Critique des postulates et axiomes de l’ecole Américaine. Econometrica, 21, 503–546. Alós-Ferrer, C. and Strack, F. (2014). From dual processes to multiple selves: Implications for economic behavior. Journal of Economic Psychology, 41, 1–11. Bardsley, N., Cubitt, R., Loomes, G., Moffatt, P., Starmer, C. and Sugden, R. (2010). Experimental Economics: Rethinking the Rules, Princeton University Press. Barsky, R. B. and Sims, E. R. (2012). Information, animal spirits, and the meaning of innovations in consumer choice. American Economic Review, 102(4), 1343–1377. Baucells, M. and Villasís, A. (2010). Stability of risky preferences and the reflection effect of prospect theory. Theory and Decision, 68, 193–211. Becker, G. M., DeGroot, M. H. and Marschak, J. (1963a). Stochastic models of choice behavior. Behavioral Science, 8, 41–55. Becker, G. M., DeGroot, M. H. and Marschak, J. (1963b). An experimental study of some stochastic models of wagers. Behavioral Science, 8, 199–202. Bernasconi, M. (1994). Nonlinear preferences and two-stage lotteries: Theories and evidence. Economic Journal, 104, 54–70. Binmore, K. (2009). Interpersonal comparison of utility. In D. Ross and H. Kincaid (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Economics (pp. 540–559). Oxford University Press: New York. Birnbaum, M. H. (2008). New paradoxes of risky decision making. Psychological Review, 115, 463–501. Birnbaum, M. H. and Jou, J. (1990). A theory of comparative response times and ‘difference’ judgments. Cognitive Psychology, 22, 184–210. Blavatskyy, P. (2006). Violations of betweenness or random errors? Economics Letters, 91, 34–38. Blavatskyy, P. (2007). Stochastic expected utility theory. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 34 (3), 259–286. Blavatskyy, P. R. (2011). A model of probabilistic choice satisfying first-order stochastic dominance. Management Science, 57, 542–548. Blavatskyy, P. R., and Pogrebna, G. (2010). Models of stochastic choice and decision theories: Why both are important for analyzing decisions. Journal of Applied Econometrics, 25, 963–986. Brandstätter, E., Gigerenzer, G. and Hertwig, R. (2006). The priority heuristic: Making choices without trade-offs. Psychological Review, 113, 409–432. Busemeyer, J. R. and Townsend, J. T. (1993). Decision field theory: A dynamic-cognitive approach to decision making in an uncertain environment. Psychological Review, 100, 432–459. Butler, D. and Loomes, G. (1988). Decision difficulty and imprecise preferences. Acta Psychologica, 68, 183–196. Butler, D., Isoni, A., Loomes, G. and Tsutsui, K. (2014a). Beyond choice: Investigating the sensitivity and validity of strength of preference measures. Experimental Economics, 17, 537–563. Butler, D., Isoni, A., Loomes, G. and Navarro-Martinez, D. (2014b). On the measurement of strength of preference in units of money. Economic Record, 90, 1–15. Calvó-Armengol, A. and Jackson, M. O. (2004). The effects of social networks on employment and inequality. American Economic Review, 94(3), 426–454. Cerreia-Vioglio, S., Dillenberger, D. and Ortoleva, P. (2015). Cautious expected utility and the certainty effect. Econometrica, 83(2), 693–728. Coombs, C. and Huang, L. (1976). Tests of the betweenness property of expected utility. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 13, 323–337. Cox, J. C. and Sadiraj, V. (2006). Small- and large-stakes risk aversion: Implications of concavity calibration for decision theory. Games and Economic Behavior, 56(1), 45–60. Dominitz, J. and Manski, C. F. (2004). How should we measure consumer confidence? Journal of Economic Perspectives, 18(2), 51–66. Elliott, M., Golub, B. and Jackson, M. O. (2014). Financial networks and contagion. American Economic Review, 104(10), 3115–3153. Elster, J. (1987). The Multiple Self. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge. Fechner, G. T. (1860/1966). Elements of psychophisic. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston. Gigerenzer, G. and Selten, R. (2001). Bounded Rationality: The Adaptive Toolbox. MIT Press. Gilboa, I. and Schmeidler, D. (1995). Case-based decision theory. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 110 (3), 605–639. Gold, J. I. and Shadlen, M. N. (2007). The neural basis of decision making. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 30, 535–574. Gouriéroux, C. and Monfort, A. (1997). Simulation-based Econometric Methods. Oxford University Press: Oxford. Hammond, P. (1993). Interpersonal comparisons of utility: Why and how they are and should be made. In J. Elster and J. Roemer (Eds.), Interpersonal Comparisons of Well-Being. Cambridge University Press: London. Harless, D. W. and Camerer, C. F. (1994). The predictive utility of generalized expected utility theories. Econometrica, 62, 1251–1289. Harstad, R. M. and Selten, R. (2013). Bounded-rationality models: Tasks to become intellectually competitive. Journal of Economic Literature, 51(2), 496–511. Hausmann, D. and Läge, D. (2008). Sequential evidence accumulation in decision making: The individual desired level of confidence can explain the extent of information acquisition. Judgment and Decision Making, 3(3), 229–43. Hey, J. D. and Orme, C. (1994). Investigating generalizations of expected utility theory using experimental data. Econometrica, 62, 1291–1326. Holt, C. A. and Laury, S. K. (2002). Risk aversion and incentive effects. American Economic Review, 92(5), 1644–1655. Jamieson, D. G. and Petrusic, W. M. (1977). Preference and time to choose. Organizational Behavior and Human Performance, 19, 56–67. Johnson, J. G. and Busemeyer, J. R. (2005), A dynamic, computational model of preference reversal phenomena. Psychological Review, 112(4), 841–861. Johnson, E. J., Häubl, G. and Keinan, A. (2007). Aspects of endowment: A query theory of value construction. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 33, 461–474. Kahneman, D. and Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect Theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–291. Kahneman, D., Rosenfield, A. M, Gandhi, L. and Blaser, T. (2016). Inconsistent decision making is a huge hidden cost for many companies. Here’s how to overcome what we call noise. Harvard Business Review, 94(10), 38–46. Kocher, M., Pahlke, J. and Trautmann, S. T. (2013). Tempus fugit: Time pressure in risky decisions. Management Science, 59(10), 2380–2391. Loomes, G. (2014). Quantitative tests of the Perceived Relative Argument Model: reply to Guo and Regenwetter. Psychological Review, 121, 706–10. Loomes, G., Moffatt, P. G. and Sugden, R. (2002). A Microeconometric test of alternative theories of risky choice. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 24, 103–130. Luce, R. D. and Suppes, P. (1965). Preferences, utility, and subjective probability. In R. D. Luce et al. (Eds.), Handbook of mathematical psychology, 3, New York: John Wiley. Luce, R. D. (1992). A theory of certainty equivalents for uncertain alternatives. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 5, 201–216. Luce, R. D., Mellers, B. and Chang, S.J. (1993). Is choice the correct primitive? On using certainty equivalents and reference levels to predict choices among gambles. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 6, 115–143. Ludvigson, S. C. (2004). Consumer confidence and consumer spending. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 18(2), 29–50. Machina, M. (1982). ‘Expected utility’ analysis without the independence axiom. Econometrica, 50, 277–323. Marschak, J. (1950). Rational behavior, uncertain prospects, and measurable utility. Econometrica, 18(2), 111–141. Moffatt, P. (2005). Stochastic choice and the allocation of cognitive effort. Experimental Economics, 8, 369–388. Moffatt, P. and Peters, S. (2001). Testing for the presence of a tremble in economic experiments. Experimental Economics, 4, 221–228. Mosteller, F. and Nogee, P. (1951). An experimental measurement of utility. Journal of Political Economy, 59, 371–404. Munier, B., Selten, R., Bouyssou, D., Bourgine, P. and Day, R. (1999). Bounded rationality modeling. Marketing Letters, 10(3), 233–248. Myers, J., Suydam, M. and Gambino, B. (1965). Contingent gains and losses in a risk-taking situation. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 2, 363–70. Otter, T., Johnson, J., Rieskamp, J., Allenby, G. M., Brazell, J. D., Diedrich, A., Hutchinson, J. W., MacEachern, S., Ruan, S. and Townsend, J. (2008). Sequential sampling models of choice: Some recent advances. Marketing Letters, 19, 255–267. Palacios-Huerta, I. and Serrano, R. (2006). Rejecting gambles under expected utility. Economics Letters, 91, 250–259. Payne, J. W., Bettman, J. R. and Johnson, E. J. (1993). The Adaptive Decision Maker. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Petrusic, W. M. and Jamieson, D. G. (1978). Relation between probability of preferential choice and time to choose changes with practice. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 4, 471–482. Pleskac, T. J. and Busemeyer, J. R. (2010). Two-stage dynamic signal detection: A theory of choice, decision time, and confidence. Psychological Review, 117, 864–901. Rabin, M. (2000). Risk aversion and expected-utility theory: A calibration theorem. Econometrica, 68(5), 1281–1292. Ratcliff, R. and Smith, P.L. (2004). A Comparison of Sequential Sampling Models for Two-Choice Reaction Time. Psychological Review, 111, 333–367. Reiss, J. (2011). A plea for (good) simulations: Nudging economics towards an experimental science. Simulation & Gaming, 42(2), 243–264. Rieskamp, J., Busemeyer, J. and Mellers, B. (2006). Extending the bounds of rationality: Evidence and theories of preferential choice. Journal of Economic Literature, 44, 631–661. Roe, R. M., Busemeyer, J. R. and Townsend, J. T. (2001). Multi-alternative decision field theory: A dynamic connectionist model of decision making. Psychological Review, 108, 370–392. Rubinstein, A. (1988). Similarity and decision making under risk: is there a utility theory resolution to the Allais paradox? Journal of Economic Theory, 46, 145–153. Rubinstein, A. (2001). Comments on the risk and time preferences in economics. Unpublished manuscript, available at http://www.econ.nyu.edu/user/bisina/rubinstein_onRabin.pdf. Rubinstein, A. (2007). Instinctive and cognitive reasoning: a study of response times. The Economic Journal, 117, 1243–1259. Rubinstein, A. (2013). Response time and decision making: an experimental study. Judgment and Decision Making, 8(5), 540–551. Rubinstein, A. (2016). Lecture Notes in Microeconomic Theory. Princeton University Press: Princeton and Oxford. Shiryaev, A. N. (1978). Optimal Stopping Rules. Springer-Verlag: Berlin Heidelberg. Sieck, W. and Yates, J.F. (1997). Exposition effects on decision making: Choice and confidence in choice. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 70, 207–219. Simon, H. A. (1978). Rationality as process and as product of thought. American Economic Review, Papers and Proceedings, 68(2), 1–16. Spiliopoulos, L. and Ortmann, A. (2016). The BCD of response time analysis in experimental economics. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2401325. Starmer, C. (2000). Developments in non-expected utility theory: The hunt for a descriptive theory of choice under risk. Journal of Economic Literature, 38, 332–382. Stewart, N., Chater, N. and Brown, G. D. A. (2006). Decision by sampling. Cognitive Psychology, 53, 1–26. Stewart, N., Reimers, S. and Harris, A. J. L. (2015). On the origin of utility, weighting, and discounting functions: How they get their shapes and how to change their shapes. Management Science, 61(3), 687–705. Stigler, G. J. (1961). The economics of information. Journal of Political Economy, 69(3), 213–225. Stott, H.P. (2006). Cumulative prospect theory’s functional menagerie. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 32, 101–130. Tversky, A. (1972). Elimination by aspects: A theory of choice. Psychological Review, 79(4), 281–299. Tversky, A. and Russo, J. E. (1969). Substitutability and similarity in binary choices. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 6, 1–12. Tyebjee, T. (1979). Response time, conflict and involvement in brand choice. Journal of Consumer Research, 6, 295–304. Wilcox, N. T. (1993). Lottery choice: Incentives, complexity and decision time. The Economic Journal, 103(421), 1397–1417. Wilcox, N. T. (2008). Stochastic models for discrete choice under risk: A critical primer and econometric comparison. In J. C. Cox and G. W. Harrison (Eds.), Research in experimental economics, 12. Bingley: Emerald Group Publishing Limited. Wilcox, N. T. (2011). ‘Stochastically more risk averse’: A contextual theory of stochastic discrete choice under risk. Journal of Econometrics, 162, 89–104. Wilcox, N. T. (2016). Random expected utility and certainty equivalents: Mimicry of probability weighting functions. MPRA Paper No. 73173. |
URI: | https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/id/eprint/79893 |