Naqvi, Nadeem (2012): Why is the Workplace Racially Segregated by Occupation?
Preview |
PDF
MPRA_paper_43352.pdf Download (717kB) | Preview |
Abstract
Ken Arrow (1998) asks, “What has economics to say about racial discrimination?” He replies – entirely correctly – that racial “segregation within an industry – that is, firms with either all black or all white labor forces” – may be explained by economic theory, but “the hypothesis of employer discrimination does not at all explain segregation by occupation, [and] discriminatory tastes of other employees … may explain segregation [by firms] within industries but not segregation by occupation[s]” (p. 95), that are filled by racially distinct persons within firms. Becker (1957) and Akerlof and Kranton (2000 and 2010) offer economic theories that deal with social identity differentiation, but these lack rational choice theory foundations, insofar as they impose a utility indicator function as a primitive concept via persuasion, rather than such a function being entailed by derivation from a preference ranking relation defined on a set of outcomes, with restrictions imposed both on the set and the relation. This is a methodological weakness of their work relative to that of Arrow and Debreu (1954). A more serious difficulty with these contributions is that they ascribe a utility function to each individual in an economy, but I prove that assigning to individuals binary preferences, with or without their numerical representation as utility indicator functions, entails the impossibility of interpersonal social-identity diversification, rendering all persons in society indistinguishable by identity. The information necessary to identify a person’s social identity is stripped off the model by the binariness restriction. A person in a binariness-salient model would simply not know against whom to discriminate. Economic theory is, therefore, endogenously color-blind, race-blind, gender-blind, ethnicity-blind, and in general, social-identity-blind. Everybody in the economy is White, or all persons are Black, or all female, or all Hispanics, and so on, but no two persons can endogenously have distinct social identities. This is also true of every player in a game, as in Nash (1951). However, if preferences are non-binary, interpersonal social identity diversification is possible, though their real-valued utility function representation is impossible. This begs the question as to what exact form preferences must take to support the specific utility function of Akerlof and Kranton, which also is non-traditional relative to the utility indicator function in Arrow and Debreu. As it happens, to exhibit diversity of persons by social identity, ascribing a utility function to a person is conceptually too restrictive. By substituting non-binary for binary preferences in the model of Arrow and Debreu, I extend their economic theory. The more general model I thus formulate has the following features: (i) there exists a social state in which all persons maximize their preferences on their feasible sets, (ii) endogenous interpersonal social-identity diversification characterizes this state of the economy, (iii) it is a free-market equilibrium without any state intervention, (iv) it is a Pareto optimal social state, and (v) a sizable proportion of Black workers are segregated into low-rank, low income jobs, whereas White workers in the same observable proficiency domain are placed in high-ranking, high-income jobs, thereby explaining occupational segregation within firms along a racial divide, which entails that (vi) income and wealth distributions vary by social identity. Thus free markets deliver a Pareto optimal state but it is fraught with remediable injustices. Further, my explanation meets standards Arrow sets for such a theory (see p. 21). (543 words)
Item Type: | MPRA Paper |
---|---|
Original Title: | Why is the Workplace Racially Segregated by Occupation? |
Language: | English |
Keywords: | justice, social identity, discrimination, race, gender, non-binariness, maximization, rational choice theory, social choice theory, general equilibrium, game theory, asymmetric information, social norms |
Subjects: | D - Microeconomics > D1 - Household Behavior and Family Economics > D11 - Consumer Economics: Theory D - Microeconomics > D6 - Welfare Economics > D63 - Equity, Justice, Inequality, and Other Normative Criteria and Measurement D - Microeconomics > D8 - Information, Knowledge, and Uncertainty > D82 - Asymmetric and Private Information ; Mechanism Design Z - Other Special Topics > Z1 - Cultural Economics ; Economic Sociology ; Economic Anthropology > Z13 - Economic Sociology ; Economic Anthropology ; Social and Economic Stratification D - Microeconomics > D5 - General Equilibrium and Disequilibrium > D51 - Exchange and Production Economies J - Labor and Demographic Economics > J1 - Demographic Economics > J16 - Economics of Gender ; Non-labor Discrimination D - Microeconomics > D4 - Market Structure, Pricing, and Design > D46 - Value Theory D - Microeconomics > D7 - Analysis of Collective Decision-Making > D71 - Social Choice ; Clubs ; Committees ; Associations D - Microeconomics > D7 - Analysis of Collective Decision-Making > D74 - Conflict ; Conflict Resolution ; Alliances ; Revolutions J - Labor and Demographic Economics > J1 - Demographic Economics > J15 - Economics of Minorities, Races, Indigenous Peoples, and Immigrants ; Non-labor Discrimination |
Item ID: | 43352 |
Depositing User: | Nadeem Naqvi |
Date Deposited: | 20 Dec 2012 22:48 |
Last Modified: | 26 Sep 2019 22:55 |
References: | Akerlof, George A. (1976), “Economics of Caste, the Rat Race and Other Woeful Tales,” Quarterly Journal of Economics, 90, 599-617. _____________ and Kranton, Rachel, E., (2000) “Economics and Identity,” Quarterly Journal of Economics, 115 (3), 715-753. _____________, (2002), “Identity and Schooling: Some Lessons for the Economics of Education,” Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XL, 1167-120. _____________, (2005), "Identity and the Economics of Organizations," Journal of Economic Perspectives, 19(1), 9-32. _____________, (2010), Identity Economics: How Our Identities Shape Our Work, Wages, and Well-Being, Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ. Arrow, Kenneth, J., (1998), “What has Economics to Say about Racial Discrimination,” Journal of Economic Perspectives, 12; 91-100. _____________ and Debreu, Gerard, (1954), “Existence of an Equilibrium for a Competitive Economy,” Econometrica, 22 (3), 265-290. Arrow, Kenneth, J and Hahn, Frank, (1971), General Competitive Analysis, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Basu, Kaushik. (2006), “Participatory Equity, Identity and Productivity: Policy Implications for Promoting Development,” BREAD Working Paper No. 119, Cornell University, May 2006, Journal of Human Development and Capabilities (forthcoming). ____________, (2010), Beyond the Invisible Hand: Groundwork for a New Economics, Penguin Books: Delhi. Becker, Gary, (1957), The Economics of Discrimination, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Berdellima, Arian and Naqvi, Nadeem, (2011), “Existence of a Pareto optimal social interaction outcome with non-binary preferences,” MPRA Paper No. 28168, online at http://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/28168/. Chipman, John S., (1970), “External Economies of Scale and Competitive Equilibrium.” Quarterly Journal of Economics, 84(336), 347–385. Deb, Rajat. (2011), “Nonbinary Social Choice,” Chapter 19, Arrow, K.J., Sen, A.K., and Suzumura K. (eds.), Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare, vol. 2, 335-366. Debreu, Gerard, (1959), Theory of Value: An Axiomatic Analysis of Economic Equilibrium, New Haven: Yale University Press. Hahn, Frank H., (1977), “Exercises in Conjectural Equilibria,” The Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 79(2), 210-226. ____________, (1978), “On Non-Walrasian Equilibria,” Review of Economic Studies, 45, 1-18. Kahneman, Daniel and Tversky, Amos, (1979), “Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk,” Econometrica, 47(2), pp. 263-291. Karni, Edi, (2005), “State-Dependent Preferences,” Johns Hopkins University Discussion Paper, June 20, 2005. Kelsey, David, (1995), "The Arbitrage Pricing Theorem with Non-Expected Utility Preferences," Journal of Economic Theory, 65, 557-574. Naqvi, Nadeem, (2010), “On Non-binary Personal Preferences in Society, Economic Theory and Racial Discrimination,” MPRA Paper No. 21522, Online at http://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/21522/. Nash, John F., (1951), " Non-cooperative Games," Annals of Mathematics, 54, 286-295. Phelps, Edmund S., (1972), “The Statistical Theory of Racism and Sexism,” American Economic Review, 62, 659-61. Sen, Amartya, K, (1970), Collective choice and social welfare, North Holland: Amsterdam; 1970. ____________, (1985), “Goals, Commitment, and Identity,” Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 1 (2), 341-355. _____________, (1989), “Cooperation, Inequality, and the Family,” Population and Development Review, 15: 61-76. _____________, (1992), “Missing women: social inequality outweighs women’s survival advantage in Asia and north Africa,” British Medical Journal, 304 (6827) p. 587-88. ____________, (1993), “Internal Consistency of Choice,” Econometrica, 61 (3): 495-521. ____________, (1994a), “The Formulation of Rational Choice,” American Economic Review, 84 (2): 745-779. _____________, (1994b), “Non-Binary Choice and Preference,” in Parawitz, Dag, Skyrms, Brian and Westrerstahl, Dag, (Eds.), Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science IX, Uppsala, Sweden, August 2-14, 1991, Elsevier: Amsterdam. ____________, (1997), “Maximization and the Act of Choice,” Econometrica, 65: 745-779. ____________, (1999), “Merit and Justice,” in Meritocracy and Economic Inequality, Kenneth Arrow, Samuel Bowles, & Steven Durlauf (eds.), Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ. ____________, (2006), Identity and Violence: The Illusion of Destiny, W.W. Norton: New York. ____________ and Williams, Bernard, (1982), “Introduction,” in Sen and Williams (Eds.) Utilitarianism and Beyond, Cambridge University Press: Cambridge. Spence, A. M. (1974), Market Signaling: Information Transfer in Hiring and Related Screening Processes, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. Stiglitz, J. (1974), “Theories of Discrimination and Economic Policy,” in G. von Furstenberg et al (eds.), Patterns of Racial Discrimination, D. C. Heath and Co. |
URI: | https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/id/eprint/43352 |